Gmail kac attac Pinker—Blank Slate kac attac Sat, Nov 11, 2023 at 9:17 AM To: Stefan Kac of brain tissue dies, a part of the mind can disappear: a neurological patient may lose the ability to name tools, recognize faces, anticipate the outcome of his behavior, empathize with others, or keep in mind a region of space or of his own body. (Descartes was thus wrong when he said that "the mind is entirely indivisible" and concluded that it must be completely different from the body.) Every emotion and thought gives off physical signals, and the new tech- ologies for detecting them are so accurate that they can literally read a per- son's mind and tell a cognitive neuroscientist whether the person is imagining a face or a place. Neuroscientists can knock a gene out of a mouse (a gene also found in humans) and prevent the mouse from learning, or insert extra copies and make the mouse learn faster. Under the microscope, brain tissue shows a staggering complexity--a hundred billion neurons connected by a hundred trillion synapses- that is commensurate with the staggering complexity of human thought and experience. Neural network modelers have begun to show how the building blocks of mental computation, such as storing and re- trieving a pattern, can be implemented in neural circuitry. And when the brain dies, the person goes out of existence. Despite concerted efforts by Alfred Rus- sel Wallace and other Victorian scientists, it is apparently not possible to com- municate with the dead. Educated people, of course, know that perception, cognition, language, and emotion are rooted in the brain. But it is still tempting to think of the brain as it was shown in old educational cartoons, as a control panel with gauges and levers operated by a user- the self, the soul, the ghost, the person, the "me." But cognitive neuroscience is showing that the self, too, is just an- other network of brain systems. The first hint came from Phineas Gage, the nineteenth-century railroad worker familiar to generations of psychology students. Gage was using a yard- long spike to tamp explosive powder into a hole in a rock when a spark ignited the powder and sent the spike into his cheekbone, through his brain, and out the top of his skull. Phineas survived with his perception, memory, language, and motor functions intact. But in the famous understatement of a co-worker, "Gage was no longer Gage." A piece of iron had literally turned him into a dif- ferent person, from courteous, responsible, and ambitious to rude, unreliable, and shiftless. It did this by impaling his ventromedial prefrontal cortex, the re- gion of the brain above the eyes now known to be involved in reasoning about other people. Together with other areas of the prefrontal lobes and the limbic system (the seat of the emotions), it anticipates the consequences of one's ac- tons and selects behavior consonant with one's goals.30 Cognitive neuroscientists have not only exorcised the ghost but have shown that the brain does not even have a part that does exactly what the ghost is supposed to do: review all the facts and make a decision for the rest of the brain to carry out."" Each of us feels that there is a single "I' in control. But that 42 / The Blank Slate, the Noble Savage, and the Ghost in the Machine is an illusion that the brain works hard to produce, like the impression that our visual fields are rich in detail from edge to edge. (In fact, we are blind to detail outside the fixation point. We quickly move our eyes to whatever looks inter- esting, and that fools us into thinking that the detail was there all along.) The brain does have supervisory systems in the prefrontal lobes and anterior cin- gulate cortex, which can push the buttons of behavior and override habits and urges. But those systems are gadgets with specific quirks and limitations; they are not implementations of the rational free agent traditionally identified with the soul or the self. One of the most dramatic demonstrations of the illusion of the unified self comes from the neuroscientists Michael Gazzaniga and Roger Sperry, who showed that when surgeons cut the corpus callosum joining the cerebral hemispheres, they literally cut the self in two, and each hemisphere can exer- cise free will without the other one's advice or consent. Even more disconcert- ingly, the left hemisphere constantly weaves a coherent but false account of the behavior chosen without its knowledge by the right. For example, if an exper- imenter flashes the command "WALK" to the right hemisphere (by keeping it in the part of the visual field that only the right hemisphere can see), the per- son will comply with the request and begin to walk out of the room. But when the person (specifically, the person's left hemisphere) is asked why he just got up, he will say, in all sincerity, "To get a Coke"-rather than "I don't really know" or "The urge just came over me" " or "You've been testing me for years since I had the surgery, and sometimes you get me to do things but I don't know exactly what you asked me to do.?" Similarly, if the patient's left hemi- sphere is shown a chicken and his right hemisphere is shown a snowfall, and both hemispheres have to select a picture that goes with what they see (each using a different hand), the left hemisphere picks a claw (correctly) and the right picks a shovel (also correctly). But when the left hemisphere is asked why the whole person made those choices, it blithely says, "Oh, that's simple. The chicken claw goes with the chicken, and you need a shovel to clean out the chicken shed.»32 The spooky part is that we have no reason to think that the baloney- generator in the patient's left hemisphere is behaving any differently from ours as we make sense of the inclinations emanating from the rest of our brains. The conscious mind- the self or soul--is a spin doctor, not the commander in chief. Sigmund Freud immodestly wrote that "humanity has in the course of time had to endure from the hands of science three great outrages upon its naive self-love": the discovery that our world is not the center of the celestial spheres but rather a speck in a vast universe, the discovery that we were not specially created but instead descended from animals, and the discovery that often our conscious minds do not control how we act but merely tell us a story about our actions. He was right about the cumulative impact, but it was The Last Wall to Fall | 43 most of the spoken vernacular by the age of three." That, too, may be an at- tempt by the genome to get our culture-acquiring apparatus online as early in life as the growing brain can handle it. OUR MINDS, THEN, are fitted with mechanisms designed to read the goals of other people so we can copy their intended acts. But why would we want to? Though we take it for granted that acquiring culture is a good thing, the act of acquiring it is often spoken of with scorn. The longshoreman and philosopher Eric Hotfer wrote, "When people are free to do as they please, they usually im- itate each other.?" And we have a menagerie of metaphors that equate this quin- essentially human ability with the behavior of animals: along with monkey see, monkey do, we have aping, parroting, sheep, lemmings, copycats, and a herd mentality. Social psychologists have amply documented that people have a powerful urge to do as their neighbors do. When unwitting subjects are surrounded by confederates of the experimenter who have been paid to do something odd, many or most will go along. They will defy their own eyes and call a long line "short" or vice versa, nonchalantly fill out a questionnaire as smoke pours out of a heating vent, or (in a Candid Camera sketch) suddenly strip down to their underwear for no apparent reason.12 But the social psychologists point out that human conformity, no matter how hilarious it looks in contrived experi- ments, has a genuine rationale in social life-_indeed, two rationales. 13 The first is informational, the desire to benefit from other people's knowl- edge and judgment. Weary veterans of committees say that the IQ of a group is the lowest IQ of any member of the group divided by the number of people in the group, but that is too pessimistic. In a species equipped with language, an intuitive psychology, and a willingness to cooperate, a group can pool the hard-won discoveries of members present and past and end up far smarter than a race of hermits. Hunter-gatherers accumulate the know-how to make tools, control fire, outsmart prey, and detoxify plants, and can live by this col- lective ingenuity even if no member could re-create it all from scratch. Also, by coordinating their behavior (say, in driving game or taking turns watching children while others forage), they can act like a big multi-headed, multi- limbed beast and accomplish feats that a die-hard individualist could not. And an array of interconnected eyes, ears, and heads is more robust than a single set with all its shortcomings and idiosyncrasies. There is a Yiddish expression of- fered as a reality check to malcontents and conspiracy theorists: The whole world isn't crazy. Much of what we call culture is simply accumulated local wisdom: ways of fashioning artifacts, selecting food, dividing up windfalls, and so on. Some an- thropologists, like Marvin Harris, argue that even practices that seem as arbi- trary as a lottery may in fact be solutions to ecological problems. ' Cows really Culture Vultures | 63 should be sacred in India, he points out; they supply food (milk and butter), fuel (dung), and power (by pulling plows), so the customs protecting them thwart the temptation to kill the goose that laid the golden egg. Other cultural differences may have a rationale in reproduction.'S In some societies, men live with their paternal families and support their wives and children; in others, they live with their maternal families and support their sisters and nieces and nephews. The second arrangement tends to be found in societies where men have to spend long periods of time away from home and adultery is relatively common, so they cannot be sure that their wives' children are theirs. Since the children of a man's mother's daughter have to be his biological kin regardless of who has been sleeping with whom, a matrilocal family allows men to invest in children who are guaranteed to carry some of their genes. Of course, only Procrustes could argue that all cultural practices have a di- rect economic or genetic payoff. The second motive for conformity is norma- tive, the desire to follow the norms of a community, whatever they are. But this, too, is not as stupidly lemminglike as it first appears. Many cultural prac- tices are arbitrary in their specific form but not in their reason for being. There is no good reason for people to drive on the right side of the road as opposed to the left side, or vice versa, but there is every reason for people to drive on the same side. So an arbitrary choice of which side to drive on, and a widespread conformity with that choice, make a great deal of sense. Other examples of ar- bitrary but coordinated choices, which economists called "cooperative equi- libria,;" include money, designated days of rest, and the pairings of sound and meaning that make up the words in a language. Shared arbitrary practices also help people cope with the fact that while many things in life are arranged along a continuum, decisions must often be binary.I Children do not become adults instantaneously, nor do dating cou- ples become monogamous partners. Rites of passage and their modern equiv- alent, pieces of paper like ID cards and marriage licenses, allow third parties to decide how to treat ambiguous cases--as a child or as an adult, as committed or as available--without endless haggling over differences of opinion. And the fuzziest categories of all are other people's intentions. Is he a loyal member of the coalition (one that I would want to have in my foxhole) or a quisling who will bail out when times get tough? Does his heart lie with his fa- ther's clan or with his father-in-law's? Is she a suspiciously merry widow or just getting on with her life? Is he dissing me or just in a hurry? Initiation rites, tribal badges, prescribed periods of mourning, and ritualized forms of address may not answer these questions definitively, but they can remove clouds of suspicion that would otherwise hang over people's heads. When conventions are widely enough entrenched, they can become a kind of reality even though they exist only in people's minds. In his book The Con- struction of Social Reality (not to be confused with the social construction of 64 / The Blank Slate, the Noble Savage, and the Ghost in the Machine homegrown technologies, and as a result they were no match for their plural- istic conquerors. Even within Eurasia and (later) the Americas, cultures that were isolated by mountainous geography-_for example, in the Appalachians, the Balkans, and the Scottish highlands--remained backward for centuries in comparison with the vast network of people around them. The extreme case, Diamond points out, is Tasmania. The Tasmanians, who were nearly exterminated by Europeans in the nineteenth century, were the most technologically primitive people in recorded history. Unlike the Ab- origines on the Australian mainland, the Tasmanians had no way of making fire, no boomerangs or spear throwers, no specialized stone tools, no axes with handles, no canoes, no sewing needles, and no ability to fish. Amazingly, the archaeological record shows that their ancestors from the Australian mainland had arrived with these technologies ten thousand years before. But then the land bridge connecting Tasmania to the mainland was submerged and the is- land was cut off from the rest of the world. Diamond speculates that any tech- nology can be lost from a culture at some point in its history. Perhaps a raw material came to be in short supply and people stopped making the products that depended on it. Perhaps all the skilled artisans in a generation were killed by a freak storm. Perhaps some prehistoric Luddite or ayatollah imposed a taboo on the practice for one inane reason or another. Whenever this happens in a culture that rubs up against other ones, the lost technology can eventually be reacquired as the people clamor for the higher standard of living enjoyed by their neighbors. But in lonely Tasmania, people would have had to reinvent the proverbial wheel every time it was lost, and so their standard of living ratch- eted downward. The ultimate irony of the Standard Social Science Model is that it failed to accomplish the very goal that brought it into being: explaining the different fortunes of human societies without invoking race. The best explanation today is thoroughly cultural, but it depends on seeing a culture as a product of human desires rather than as a shaper of them. HISTORY AND CULTURE, then, can be grounded in psychology, which can be grounded in computation, neuroscience, genetics, and evolution. But this kind of talk sets off alarms in the minds of many nonscientists. They fear that consilience is a smokescreen for a hostile takeover of the humanities, arts, and social sciences by philistines in white coats. The richness of their subject mat- ter would be dumbed down into a generic palaver about neurons, genes, and evolutionary urges. This scenario is often called "reductionism," and I will conclude the chapter by showing why consilience does not call for it. Reductionism, like cholesterol, comes in good and bad forms. Bad reduc tionism-also called "greedy reductionism" or "destructive reductionism" consists of trying to explain a phenomenon in terms of its smallest or simplest Culture Vultures / 69 constituents. Greedy reductionism is not a straw man. I know several scientists who believe (or at least say to granting agencies) that we will make break- throughs in education, conflict resolution, and other social concerns by study- ing the biophysics of neural membranes or the molecular structure of the synapse. But greedy reductionism is far from the majority view, and it is easy to show why it is wrong. As the philosopher Hilary Putnam has pointed out, even the simple fact that a square peg won't fit into a round hole cannot be ex- plained in terms of molecules and atoms but only at a higher level of analysis involving rigidity (regardless of what makes the peg rigid) and geometry,26 And if anyone really thought that sociology or literature or history could be re- placed by biology, why stop there? Biology could in turn be ground up into chemistry, and chemistry into physics, leaving one struggling to explain the causes of World War I in terms of electrons and quarks. Even if World War I consisted of nothing but a very, very large number of quarks in a very, very complicated pattern of motion, no insight is gained by describing it that way. Good reductionism (also called hierarchical reductionism) consists not of replacing one field of knowledge with another but of connecting or unifying them. The building blocks used by one field are put under a microscope by an- other. The black boxes get opened; the promissory notes get cashed. A geogra- pher might explain why the coastline of Africa fits into the coastline of the Americas by saying that the landmasses were once adjacent but sat on differ- ent plates, which drifted apart. The question of why the plates move gets passed on to the geologists, who appeal to an upwelling of magma that pushes them apart. As for how the magma got so hot, they call in the physicists to ex- plain the reactions in the Earth's core and mantle. None of the scientists is dis- pensable. An isolated geographer would have to invoke magic to move the continents, and an isolated physicist could not have predicted the shape of South America. So, too, for the bridge between biology and culture. The big thinkers in the sciences of human nature have been adamant that mental life has to be under- stood at several levels of analysis, not just the lowest one. The linguist Noam Chomsky, the computational neuroscientist David Marr, and the ethologist Niko Tinbergen have independently marked out a set of levels of analysis for understanding a faculty of the mind. These levels include its function (what it accomplishes in an ultimate, evolutionary sense); its real-time operation (how it works proximately, from moment to moment); how it is implemented in neural tissue; how it develops in the individual; and how it evolved in the species.? For example, language is based on a combinatorial grammar de- signed to communicate an unlimited number of thoughts. It is utilized by people in real time via an interplay of memory lookup and rule application. It is implemented in a network of regions in the center of the left cerebral hemi- sphere that must coordinate memory, planning, word meaning, and grammar. 70 / The Blank Slate, the Noble Savage, and the Ghost in the Machine study of culture. Sociobiology challenges the integrity of culture as a thing-in- itself, as a distinctive and symbolic human creation."I0 Sahlins's book was called The Use and Abuse of Biology. An example of the alleged abuse was the idea that Hamilton's theory of inclusive fitness could help explain the importance of family ties in human life. Hamilton had shown how a tendency to make sacrifices for relatives could have evolved. Relatives share genes, so any gene that nudges an organism to help a relative would be indirectly helping a copy of itself. The gene will proliferate if the cost incurred by the favor is less than the benefit conferred to the relative, discounted by the degree of relatedness (one-half for a full sibling or offspring, one-eighth for a first cousin, and so on). That can't be true, Sahlins wrote, because people in most cultures don't have words for fractions. This leaves them unable to figure out the coefficients of relatedness that would tell them which relatives to favor and by how much. His objection is a textbook confusion of a proximate cause with an ultimate cause. It is like saying that people can't possibly see in depth, because most cultures haven't worked out the trigonometry that underlies stereoscopic vision. In any case, "vulgar" wasn't the half of it. Following a favorable review in the New York Review of Books by the distinguished biologist C. H. Waddington, the "Sociobiology Study Group" (including two of Wilson's colleagues, the pa- leontologist Stephen Jay Gould and the geneticist Richard Lewontin) pub- lished a widely circulated philippic called "Against 'Sociobiology!" After lumping Wilson with proponents of eugenics, Social Darwinism, and Jensen's hypothesis of innate racial differences in intelligence, the signatories wrote: The reason for the survival of these recurrent determinist theories is that they consistently tend to provide a genetic justification of the status quo and of existing privileges for certain groups according to class, race, or sex.... These theories provided an important basis for the enact- ment of sterilization laws and restrictive immigration laws by the United States between 1910 and 1930 and also for the eugenics policies which led to the establishment of gas chambers in Nazi Germany. ... What Wilson's book illustrates to us is the enormous difficulty in separating out not only the effects of environment (e.g., cultural transmission) but also the personal and social class prejudices of the re- searcher. Wilson joins the long parade of biological determinists whose work has served to buttress the institutions of their society by exonerat- ing them from responsibility for social problems." They also accused Wilson of discussing "the salutary advantages of geno- cide" and of making "institutions such as slavery ... seem natural in human societies because of their universal' existence in the biological kingdom." In Political Scientists / 109 Asymmetry. It is "an essential truth," he writes, that "good and kind people outnumber all others by thousands to one."I2 Moreover, "we perform 10,000 acts of small and unrecorded kindness for each surpassingly rare, but sadly balancing, moment of cruelty,"'3 The statistics making up this "essential truth" are pulled out of the air and are certainly wrong: psychopaths, who are defi- nitely not "good and kind people," make up about three or four percent of the male population, not several hundredths of a percent.'A But even if we accept the figures, the argument assumes that for a species to count as "evil and de- Taleb', structive," it would have to be evil and destructive all the time, like a deranged postal worker on a permanent rampage. It is precisely because one act can bal- plane ance ten thousand kind ones that we call it "evil." Also, does it make sense to crash judge our entire species, as if we were standing en masse at the pearly gates? The issue is not whether our species is "evil and destructive" but whether we house evil and destructive motives, together with the beneficent and construc- tive ones. If we do, one can try to understand what they are and how they work. Gould has objected to any attempt to understand the motives for war in the context of human evolution, because "each case of genocide can be matched with numerous incidents of social beneficence; each murderous band can be paired with a pacific clan."'IS Once again a ratio has been conjured out of the blue; the data reviewed in Chapter 3 show that "pacific clans" either do not exist or are considerably outnumbered by the "murderous bands."16 But for Gould, such facts are beside the point, because he finds it necessary to believe in the pacific clans on moral grounds. Only if humans lack any predis- position for good or evil or anything else, he suggests, do we have grounds for opposing genocide. Here is how he imagines the position of the evolutionary psychologists he disagrees with: Perhaps the most popular of all explanations for our genocidal capacity cites evolutionary biology as an unfortunate source-_and as an ultimate escape from full moral responsibility... . A group devoid of xenopho- bia and unschooled in murder might invariably succumb to others re- plete with genes to encode a propensity for such categorization and destruction. Chimpanzees, our closest relatives, will band together and systematically kill the members of adjacent groups. Perhaps we are pro- grammed to act in such a manner as well. These grisly propensities once promoted the survival of groups armed with nothing more destructive than teeth and stones. In a world of nuclear bombs, such unchanged (and perhaps unchangeable) inheritances may now spell our undoing (or at least propagate our tragedies)-_-but we cannot be blamed for these moral failings. Our accursed genes have made us creatures of the night. I7 The Holy Trinity / 125 equality and human rights) should not be held hostage to some factual con- jecture about blank slates that might be refuted tomorrow. In this chapter we will see how these values might be put on a more secure foundation. WHAT KINDS OF differences are there to worry about? The chapters on gender and children will review the current evidence on differences between sexes and individuals, together with their implications and non-implications. The goal of this part of the chapter is more general: to lay out the kinds of differences that research could turn up over the long term, based on our understanding of human evolution and genetics, and to lay out the moral issues they raise. This book is primarily about human nature-_-an endowment of cognitive and emotional faculties that is universal to healthy members of Homo sapiens. Samuel Johnson wrote, "We are all prompted by the same motives, all deceived by the same fallacies, all animated by hope, obstructed by danger, entangled by desire, and seduced by pleasure." The abundant evidence that we share a human nature does not mean that the differences among individuals, races, or sexes are also in our nature. Confucius could have been right when he wrote, "Men's natures are alike; it is their habits that carry them far apart."? Modern biology tells us that the forces that make people alike are not the same as the forces that make people different.° (Indeed, they tend to be stud- ed by different scientists: the similarities by evolutionary psychologists, the differences by behavioral geneticists.) Natural selection works to homogenize a species into a standard overall design by concentrating the effective genes- the ones that build well-functioning organs-_and winnowing out the ineffec- tive ones. When it comes to an explanation of what makes us tick, we are thus birds of a feather. Just as we all have the same physical organs (two eyes, a liver, a four-chambered heart), we have the same mental organs. This is most obvi- ous in the case of language, where every neurologically intact child is equipped to acquire any human language, but it is true of other parts of the mind as well. Discarding the Blank Slate has thrown far more light on the psychological unity of humankind than on any differences. 4 We are all pretty much alike, but we are not, of course, clones. Except in the case of identical twins, each person is genetically unique. That is because random mutations infiltrate the genome and take time to be eliminated, and they are shuffled together in new combinations when individuals sexually re- produce. Natural selection tends to preserve some degree of genetic hetero- geneity at the microscopic level in the form of small, random variations among proteins. That variation twiddles the combinations of an organism's molecular locks and keeps its descendants one step ahead of the microscopic germs that are constantly evolving to crack those locks. All species harbor genetic variability, but Homo sapiens is among the less variable ones. Geneticists call us a "small" species, which sounds like a bad joke 142 / Human Nature with a Human Face given that we have infested the planet like roaches. What they mean is that the amount of genetic variation found among humans is what a biologist would, expect in a species with a small number of members. There are more genetic differences among chimpanzees, for instance, than there are among humans, even though we dwarf them in number. The reason is that our ancestors passed through a population bottleneck fairly recently in our evolutionary history (less than a hundred thousand years ago) and dwindled to a small number of individuals with a correspondingly small amount of genetic varia- tion. The species survived and rebounded, and then underwent a population explosion after the invention of agriculture about ten thousand years ago. That explosion bred many copies of the genes that were around when we were sparse in number; there has not been much time to accumulate many new ver- sions of the genes. At various points after the bottleneck, differences between races emerged. But the differences in skin and hair that are so obvious when we look at peo- ple of other races are really a trick played on our intuitions. Racial differences are largely adaptations to climate. Skin pigment was a sunscreen for the trop- is, eyelid folds were goggles for the tundra. The parts of the body that face the elements are also the parts that face the eyes of other people, which fools them into thinking that racial differences run deeper than they really do.' Working in opposition to the adaptation to local climates, which makes groups differ- ent on the skin, is an evolutionary force that makes neighboring groups simi- lar inside. Rare genes can offer immunity to endemic diseases, so they get sucked into one group from a neighboring group like ink on a blotter, even if members of one group mate with members of the other infrequently.? That is why Jews, for example, tend to be genetically similar to their non-Jewish neighbors all over the world, even though until recently they tended to marry other Jews. As little as one conversion, affair, or rape involving a gentile in every generation can be enough to blur genetic boundaries over time. Taking all these processes into account, we get the following picture. Peo- ple are qualitatively the same but may differ quantitatively. The quantitative differences are small in biological terms, and they are found to a far greater ex- tent among the individual members of an ethnic group or race than between ethnic groups or races. These are reassuring findings. Any racist ideology that holds that the members of an ethnic group are all alike, or that one ethnic group differs fundamentally from another, is based on false assumptions about our biology. But biology does not let us off the hook entirely. Individuals are not ge- netically identical, and it is unlikely that the differences affect every part of the body except the brain. And though genetic differences between races and ethnic groups are much smaller than those among individuals, they are not nonexistent (as we see in their ability to give rise to physical differences and to The Fear of Inequality / 143 Y sh intellect, moral development or social capacity, but only in respect to "certain inalienable rights." 12 Some of the most influential contemporary thinkers about biology and human nature have drawn the same distinction. Ernst Mayr, one of the found. ers of the modern theory of evolution, wisely anticipated nearly four decades of debate when he wrote in 1963: dero 2/b Equality in spite of evident nonidentity is a somewhat sophisticated concept and requires a moral stature of which many individuals seem to be incapable. They rather deny human variability and equate equality with identity. Or they claim that the human species is exceptional in the organic world in that only morphological characters are controlled by genes and all other traits of the mind or character are due to "condition- ing" or other nongenetic factors. Such authors conveniently ignore the results of twin studies and of the genetic analysis of nonmorphological traits in animals. An ideology based on such obviously wrong premises can only lead to disaster. Its championship of human equality is based on a claim of identity. As soon as it is proved that the latter does not exist, the support of equality is likewise lost. 13 Noam Chomsky made the same point in an article entitled "Psychology and Ideology." Though he disagreed with Herrnstein's argument about IQ (dis- cussed in Chapter 6), he denied the popular charge that Herrnstein was a racist and distanced himself from fellow radical scientists who were denouncing the facts as dangerous: A correlation between race and IQ (were this shown to exist) entails no social consequences except in a racist society in which each individual is assigned to a racial category and dealt with not as an individual in his own right, but as a representative of this category. Herrnstein mentions a possible correlation between height and IQ. Of what social impor- tance is that? None of course, since our society does not suffer under discrimination by height. We do not insist on assigning each adult to the category "below six feet in height" or "above six feet in height" when we ask what sort of education he should receive or where he should live or what work he should do. Rather, he is what he is, quite independent of the mean IQ of people of his height category. In a nonracist society, the category of race would be of no greater significance. The mean IQ of in- dividuals of a certain racial background is irrelevant to the situation of a particular individual who is what he is.. It is, incidentally, surprising to me that so many commentators should find it disturbing that IQ might be heritable, perhaps largely s0. 146 / Human Nature with a Human Face Would it also be disturbing to discover that relative height or musical talent or rank in running the one-hundred-yard dash is in part geneti- cally determined? Why should one have preconceptions one way or an- other about these questions, and how do the answers to them, whatever they may be, relate either to serious scientific issues (in the present state of our knowledge) or to social practice in a decent society?14 Some readers may not be reassured by this lofty stance. If all ethnic groups and both sexes were identical in all talents, then discrimination would simply be self-defeating, and people would abandon it as soon as the facts were known. But if they are not identical, it would be rational to take those differ- ences into account. After all, according to Bayes' theorem a decision maker who needs to make a prediction (such as whether a person will succeed in a profession) should factor in the prior probability, such as the base rate of suc- cess for people in that group. If races or sexes are different on average, racial profiling or gender stereotyping would be actuarially sound, and it would be naive to expect information about race and sex not to be used for prejudicial ends. So a policy to treat people as individuals seems like a thin reed on which to hang any hope of reducing discrimination. An immediate reply to this worry is that the danger arises whether the dif- ferences between groups are genetic or environmental in origin. An average is an average, and an actuarial decision maker should care only about what it is, not what caused it. Moreover, the fact that discrimination can be economically rational would be truly dangerous only if our policies favored ruthless economic optimization regardless of all other costs. But in fact we have many policies that allow moral principles to trump economic efficiency. For example, it is illegal to sell your vote, sell your organs, or sell your children, even though an economist could argue that any voluntary exchange leaves both parties better off. These deci- sions come naturally in modern democracies, and we can just as resolutely choose public policies and private mores that disallow race and gender preju- dice.I5 Moral and legal proscriptions are not the only way to reduce discrimina- tion in the face of possible group differences. The more information we have about the qualifications of an individual, the less impact a race-wide or sex- wide average would have in any statistical decision concerning that person. The best cure for discrimination, then, is more accurate and more extensive testing of mental abilities, because it would provide so much predictive infor- mation about an individual that no one would be tempted to factor in race or gender. (This, however, is an idea with no political future.) Discrimination-in the sense of using a statistically predictive trait of an individual's group to make a decision about the individual- is not always The Fear of Inequality / 147 immoral, or at least we don't always treat it as immoral. To predict someone's behavior perfectly we would need an X-ray machine for the soul. Even pre- dicting someone's behavior with the tools we do have such as tests, inter. views, background checks, and recommendations-_Would require unlimited resources if we were to use them to the fullest. Decisions that have to be made with finite time and resources, and which have high costs for certain kinds of errors, must use some trait as a basis for judging a person. And that necessarily judges the person according to a stereotype. In some cases the overlap between two groups is so small that we feel com- fortable discriminating against one of the groups absolutely. For example, no one objects to keeping chimpanzees out of our schools, even though it is con- ceivable that if we tested every chimp on the planet we might find one that could learn to read and write. We apply a speciesist stereotype that chimps cannot profit from a human education, figuring that the odds of finding an ex- ception do not outweigh the costs of examining every last one. In more realistic circumstances we have to decide on a case-by-case basis whether the discrimination is justifiable. Denying driving and voting rights to young teenagers is a form of age discrimination that is unfair to responsible teens. But we are not willing to pay either the financial costs of developing a test for psychological maturity or the moral costs of classification errors, such as teens wrapping their cars around trees. Almost everyone is appalled by racial profiling pulling over motorists for "driving while black" But after the 2001 terrorist attacks on the World Trade Center and the Pentagon, about half of Americans polled said they were not opposed to ethnic profiling-_scrutinizing passengers for "flying while Arab." 6 People who distinguish the two must rea- son that the benefits of catching a marijuana dealer do not outweigh the harm done to innocent black drivers, but the benefits of stopping a suicide hijacker do outweigh the harm done to innocent Arab passengers. Cost-benefit analy- ses are also sometimes used to justify racial preferences: the benefits of racially diverse workplaces and campuses are thought to outweigh the costs of dis- criminating against whites. The possibility that men and women are not the same in all respects also presents policymakers with choices. It would be reprehensible for a bank to hire a man over a woman as a manager for the reason that he is less likely to quit after having a child. Would it also be reprehensible for a couple to hire a Woman over a man as a nanny for their daughter because she is less likely to sexually abuse the child? Most people believe that the punishment for a given crime should be the same regardless of who commits it. But knowing the typ- ical sexual emotions of the two sexes, should we apply the same punishment to a man who seduces a sixteen-year-old girl and to a woman who seduces à sixteen-year-old boy? These are some of the issues that face the people of a democracy in decid- 148 / Human Nature with a Human Face considering student admissions, in hiring faculty and staff, and especially in their gossip about one another. Nor can citizens or policymakers ignore the concept, regardless of their politics. People who say that IQ is meaningless will quickly invoke it when the discussion turns to executing a murderer with an IQ of 64, removing lead paint that lowers a child's IQ by five points, or the presidential qualifications of George W. Bush. In any case, there is now ample evidence that intelligence is a stable property of an individual, that it can be linked to features of the brain (including overall size, amount of gray matter in the frontal lobes, speed of neural conduction, and metabolism of cerebral glu- cose), that it is partly heritable among individuals, and that it predicts some of the variation in life outcomes such as income and social status,20 The existence of inborn talents, however, does not call for Social Darwin- ism. The anxiety that one must lead to the other is based on two fallacies. The first is an all-or-none mentality that often infects discussions of the social im- plications of genetics. The likelihood that inborn differences are one contribu- tor to social status does not mean that it is the only contributor. The other ones include sheer luck, inherited wealth, race and class prejudice, unequal oppor- tunity (such as in schooling and connections), and cultural capital: habits and values that promote economic success. Acknowledging that talent matters doesn't mean that prejudice and unequal opportunity do not matter. But more important, even if inherited talents can lead to socioeconomic success, it doesn't mean that the success is deserved in a moral sense. Social Darwinism is based on Spencer's assumption that we can look to evolution to discover what is right--that "good" can be boiled down to "evolutionarily suc- cessful.?" This lives in infamy as a reference case for the "naturalistic fallacy": the belief that what happens in nature is good. (Spencer also confused people's social success--their wealth, power, and status--with their evolutionary suc- cess, the number of their viable descendants.) The naturalistic fallacy was named by the moral philosopher G. E. Moore in his 1903 Principia Ethica, the book that killed Spencer's ethics.?' Moore applied "Hume's Guillotine," the ar- gument that no matter how convincingly you show that something is true, it never follows logically that it ought to be true. Moore noted that it is sensible to ask, "This conduct is more evolutionarily successful, but is it good?" The mere fact that the question makes sense shows that evolutionary success and goodness are not the same thing. Can one really reconcile biological differences with a concept of social jus- tice? Absolutely. In his famous theory of justice, the philosopher John Rawls asks us to imagine a social contract drawn up by self-interested agents negoti- ating under a veil of ignorance, unaware of the talents or status they will in- herit at birth- ghosts ignorant of the machines they will haunt. He argues that a just society is one that these disembodied souls would agree to be born into, knowing that they might be dealt a lousy social or genetic hand.?? If you agree 150 / Human Nature with a Human Face that this is a reasonable conception of justice, and that the agents would insist on a broad social safety net and redistributive taxation (short of eliminating incentives that make everyone better off), then you can justify compensatory social policies even if you think differences in social status are 100 percent ge- metic. The policies would be, quite literally, a matter of justice, not a conse- quence of the indistinguishability of individuals. Indeed, the existence of innate differences in ability makes Rawls's con- ception of social justice especially acute and eternally relevant. If we were blank slates, and if a society ever did eliminate discrimination, the poorest could be said to deserve their station because they must have chosen to do less with their standard-issue talents. But if people differ in talents, people might find themselves in poverty in a nonprejudiced society even if they applied themselves to the fullest. That is an injustice that, a Rawlsian would argue, ought to be rectified, and it would be overlooked if we didn't recognize that people differ in their abilities. SOME PEOPLE HAVE suggested to me that these grandiloquent arguments are just too fancy for the dangerous world we live in. Granted, there is evidence that people are different, but since data in the social sciences are never perfect, and since a conclusion of inequality might be used to the worst ends by bigots or Social Darwinists, shouldn't we err on the side of caution and stick with the null hypothesis that people are identical? Some believe that even if we were certain that people differ genetically, we might still want to promulgate the fic- tion that they are the same, because it is less open to abuse. This argument is based on the fallacy that the Blank Slate has nothing but good moral implications and a theory of human nature nothing but bad ones. In the case of human differences, as in the case of human universals, the dangers go both ways. If people in different stations are mistakenly thought to differ in their inherent ability, we might overlook discrimination and un- equal opportunity. In Darwin's words, "If the misery of the poor be caused not by the laws of nature, but by our institutions, great is our sin." But if peo- ple in different stations are mistakenly thought to be the same, then we might envy them the rewards they've earned fair and square and might implement coercive policies to hammer down the nails that stick up. The economist Friedrich Hayek wrote, "It is just not true that humans are born equal;.. if We treat them equally, the result must be inequality in their actual posi- ton;... [thus] the only way to place them in an equal position would be to treat them differently. Equality before the law and material equality are, therefore, not only different but in conflict with each other,"3 The phi- losophers Isaiah Berlin, Karl Popper, and Robert Nozick have made similar points. Unequal treatment in the name of equality can take many forms. Some The Fear of Inequality / 151 Forms have both defenders and detractors, such as soak-the-rich taxation, heavy estate taxes, streaming by age rather than ability in schools, quotas and pref erences that favor certain races or regions, and prohibitions against private medical care or other voluntary transactions. But some can be downright dan- gerous. If people are assumed to start out identical but some end up wealthier than others, observers may conclude that the wealthier ones must be more ra- pacious. And as the diagnosis slides from talent to sin, the remedy can shift from redistribution to vengeance. Many atrocities of the twentieth century were com- mitted in the name of egalitarianism, targeting people whose success was taken as evidence of their criminality. The kulaks ("bourgeois peasants") were exter- minated by Lenin and Stalin in the Soviet Union; teachers, former landlords, and "rich peasants" were humiliated, tortured, and murdered during China's Cultural Revolution; city dwellers and literate professionals were worked to death or executed during the reign of the Khmer Rouge in Cambodia.? Edu- cated and entrepreneurial minorities who have prospered in their adopted re- gions, such as the Indians in East Africa and Oceania, the Ibos in Nigeria, the Armenians in Turkey, the Chinese in Indonesia and Malaysia, and the Jews al- most everywhere, have been expelled from their homes or killed in pogroms be- cause their visibly successful members were seen as parasites and exploiters, 25 A nonblank slate means that a tradeoff between freedom and material equality is inherent to all political systems. The major political philosophies can be defined by how they deal with the tradeoff. The Social Darwinist right places no value on equality; the totalitarian left places no value on freedom. The Rawlsian left sacrifices some freedom for equality; the libertarian right sacrifices some equality for freedom. While reasonable people may disagree about the best tradeoff, it is unreasonable to pretend there is no tradeoff. And that in turn means that any discovery of innate differences among individuals is not forbidden knowledge to be suppressed but information that might help us decide on these tradeoffs in an intelligent and humane manner. THE SPECTER OF eugenics can be disposed of as easily as the specters of dis- crimination and Social Darwinism. Once again, the key is to distinguish bio- logical facts from human values. If people differ genetically in intelligence and character, could we selec- tively breed for smarter and nicer people? Possibly, though the intricacies of genetics and development would make it far harder than the fans of eugenics imagined. Selective breeding is straightforward for genes with additive ef tects that is, genes that have the same impact regardless of the other genes in the genome. But some traits, such as scientific genius, athletic virtuosity, and musical giftedness, are what behavioral geneticists call emergenic: they mate, rialize only with certain combinations of genes and therefore don't "breed true.?"2 Moreover, a given gene can lead to different behavior in different en- 152 / Human Nature with a Human Face explanation; if behavior were utterly random, we couldn't hold the person re- sponsible in any case. So if we ever hold people responsible for their behavior, it will have to be in spite of any causal explanation we feel is warranted, whether it invokes genes, brains, evolution, media images, self-doubt, bringing up-ke, or being raised by bickering women. The difference between explaining behavior and excusing it is captured in the saying "To understand is not to for. give," and has been stressed in different ways by many philosophers, including Hume, Kant, and Sartre. 13 Most philosophers believe that unless a person was literally coerced (that is, someone held a gun to his head), we should consider his actions to have been freely chosen, even if they were caused by events inside his skull. But how can we have both explanation, with its requirement of lawful cau- sation, and responsibility, with its requirement of free choice? To have them both we don't need to resolve the ancient and perhaps unresolvable antinomy between free will and determinism. We only have to think clearly about what We want the notion of responsibility to achieve. Whatever may be its inherent abstract worth, responsibility has an eminently practical function: deterring harmful behavior. When we say that we hold someone responsible for a wrongful act, we expect him to punish himself--by compensating the victim, acquiescing to humiliation, incurring penalties, or expressing credible re- morse-and we reserve the right to punish him ourselves. Unless a person is willing to suffer some unpleasant (and hence deterring) consequence, claims of responsibility are hollow. Richard Nixon was ridiculed when he bowed to pressure and finally "took responsibility" for the Watergate burglary but did not accept any costs such as apologizing, resigning, or firing his aides. One reason to hold someone responsible is to deter the person from com- mitting similar acts in the future. But that cannot be the whole story, because it is different only in degree from the contingencies of punishment used by be- haviorists to modify the behavior of animals. In a social, language-using, rea- soning organism, the policy can also deter similar acts by other organisms who learn of the contingencies and control their behavior so as not to incur the penalties. That is the ultimate reason we feel compelled to punish elderly Nazi war criminals, even though there is little danger that they would perpetrate another holocaust if we let them die in their beds in Bolivia. By holding them responsible- that is, by publicly enforcing a policy of rooting out and punish- ing evil wherever and whenever it occurs- we hope to deter others from com- mitting comparable evils in the future. This is not to say that the concept of responsibility is a recommendation by policy wonks for preventing the largest number of harmful acts at the least cost. Even if experts had determined that punishing a Nazi would prevent no future atrocities, or that we could save more lives by diverting the manpower to catching drunk drivers, we would still want to bring Nazis to justice. The de- 180 / Human Nature with a Human Face responsible for his crimes, until the contrary be proved to their satisfac- tion; and that, to establish a defense on the ground of insanity, it must be clearly proved that, at the time of the committing of the act, the party accused was laboring under such a defect of reason, from disease of the mind, as not to know the nature and quality of the act he was doing, or, if he did know it, that he did not know he was doing what was wrong. This is an excellent characterization of a person who cannot be deterred. If someone is too addled to know that an act would harm someone, he cannot be inhibited by the injunction "Don't harm people, or else!" The MNaughten rule aims to forgo spiteful punishment--retribution that harms the perpetra- tor with no hope of deterring him or people similar to him. The insanity defense achieved its present notoriety, with dueling rent-a- shrinks and ingenious abuse excuses, when it was expanded from a practical test of whether the cognitive system responding to deterrence is working to the more nebulous tests of what can be said to have produced the behavior. In the 1954 Durham decision, Bazelon invoked "the science of psychiatry" and "the science of psychology" to create a new basis for the insanity defense: The rule we now hold is simply that an accused is not criminally re- sponsible if his unlawful act was the product of mental disease or men- tal defect. Unless one believes that ordinary acts are chosen by a ghost in the machine, all acts are products of cognitive and emotional systems in the brain. Criminal acts are relatively rare-_-if everyone in a defendant's shoes acted as he did, the law against what he did would be repealed- so heinous acts will often be products of a brain system that is in some way different from the norm, and the behavior can be construed as "a product of mental disease or mental defect." The Durham decision and similar insanity rules, by distinguishing behavior that is a product of a brain condition from behavior that is something else, threatens to turn every advance in our understanding of the mind into an ero- son of responsibility. Now, some discoveries about the mind and brain really could have an im- pact on our attitudes toward responsibility--but they may call for expanding the domain of responsibility, not contracting it. Suppose desires that some times culminate in the harassment and battering of women are present in many men. Does that really mean that men should be punished more leniently for such crimes, because they can't help it? Or does it mean they should be punished more surely and severely, because that is the best way to counteract a strong or widespread urge? Suppose a vicious psychopath is found to have a defective sense of sympathy, which makes it harder for him to appreciate the 184 / Human Nature with a Human Face suffering of his victims. Should we mitigate the punishment because he has di- minished capacity? Or should we make the punishment more sure and severe to teach him a lesson in the only language he understands? Why do people's intuitions go in opposite directions-_-both "If he has trouble controlling himself, he should be punished more leniently" and "If he has trouble controlling himself, he should be punished more severely? It goes back to the deterrence paradox. Suppose some people need a threat of one lash with a wet noodle to deter them from parking in front of a fire hydrant. Sup- pose people with a bad gene, a bad brain, or a bad childhood need the threat of ten lashes. A policy that punishes illegal parkers with nine lashes will cause unnecessary suffering and not solve the problem: nine lashes is more than nec- essary to deter ordinary people and less than necessary to deter defective peo- ple. Only a penalty of ten lashes can reduce both illegal parking and lashing: everyone will be deterred, no one will block hydrants, and no one will get whipped. So, paradoxically, the two extreme policies (harsh punishment and no punishment) are defensible and the intermediate ones are not. Of course, people's deterrence thresholds in real life aren't pinned at just two values but are broadly distributed (one lash for some people, two for others, and so on), so many intermediate levels of punishment will be defensible, depending on how one weights the benefits of deterring wrongdoing against the costs of in flicting harm. Even for those who are completely undeterrable, because of frontal-lobe damage, genes for psychopathy, or any other putative cause, we do not have to allow lawyers to loose them on the rest of us. We already have a mechanism for those likely to harm themselves or others but who do not respond to the carrots and sticks of the criminal justice system: involuntary civil commitment, in which we trade off some guarantees of civil liberties against the security of being protected from likely predators. In all these decisions, the sciences of human nature can help estimate the distribution of deterrabilities, but they can- not weight the conflicting values of avoiding the greatest amount of unneces- Sary punishment and preventing the greatest amount of future wrongdoing.' I do not claim to have solved the problem of free will, only to have shown that we don't need to solve it to preserve personal responsibility in the face of an increasing understanding of the causes of behavior. Nor do I argue that deterrence is the only way to encourage virtue, just that we should recognize it as the active ingredient that makes responsibility worth keeping. Most of all, I hope I have dispelled two fallacies that have allowed the sciences of human nature to sow unnecessary fear. The first fallacy is that biological ex- planations corrode responsibility in a way that environmental explanations do not. The second fallacy is that causal explanations (both biological and en- vironmental) corrode responsibility in a way that a belief in an uncaused will or soul does not. The Fear of Determinism / 185 The euphemism treadmill shows that concepts, not words, are primary in people's minds. Give a concept a new name, and the name becomes colored by the concept; the concept does not become freshened by the name, at least not for long. Names for minorities will continue to change as long as people have negative attitudes toward them. We will know that we have achieved mutual respect when the names stay put. "IMAGE IS NOTHING. Thirst is everything,"' screams a soft-drink ad that tries to create a new image for its product by making fun of soft-drink ads that try to create images for their products. Like words, images are salient tokens of our mental lives. And like words, images are said to have an insidious power over our consciousness, presumably because they are inscribed directly onto a blank slate. In postmodernist and relativist thinking, images are held to shape our view of reality, or to be our view of reality, or to be reality itself. This is es- pecially true of images representing celebrities, politicians, women, and AHANAs. And as with language, the scientific study of imagery shows that the fear is misplaced. A good description of the standard view of images within cultural studies and related disciplines may be found in the Concise Glossary of Cultural The- ory. It defines image as a "mental or visual representation of an object or event as depicted in the mind, a painting, a photograph, or film." Having thus run together images in the world (such as paintings) with images in the mind, the entry lays out the centrality of images in postmodernism, cultural studies, and academic feminism. First it notes, reasonably enough, that images can misrepresent reality and thereby serve the interests of an ideology. A racist caricature, presumably, is a prime example. But then it takes the concept further: With what is called the "crisis of representation" brought about by postmodernism, however, it is often questioned whether an image can be thought to simply represent, or misrepresent, a supposedly prior or external, image-free reality. Reality is seen rather as always subject to, or as the product of, modes of representation. In this view we inescapably inhabit a world of images or representations and not a "real world" and true or false images of it. In other words, if a tree falls in a forest and there is no artist to paint it, not only did the tree make no sound, but it did not fall, and there was no tree there to begin with. In a further move. we are thought to exist in a world of HYPERREAL- Ty, in which images are self-generating and entirely detached from any In Touch with Reality / 213 this way of thinking comes easily to Americans as well. © It appears to be the core of our intuitive economics. Fiske contrasts Equality Matching with a very different system called Mar. ket Pricing, the system of rents, prices, wages, and interest rates that underlies modern economies. Market Pricing relies on the mathematics of multiplica- tion, division, fractions, and large numbers, together with the social institu- tions of money, credit, written contracts, and complex divisions of labor. Market Pricing is absent in hunter-gatherer societies, and we know it played no role in our evolutionary history because it relies on technologies like writ- ing, money, and formal mathematics, which appeared only recently. Even today the exchanges carried out by Market Pricing may involve causal chains that are impossible for any individual to grasp in full. I press some keys to enter characters into this manuscript today and entitle myself to receive some groceries years from now, not because I will barter a copy of The Blank Slate to a banana grower but because of a tangled web of third and fourth and fifth parties (publishers, booksellers, truckers, commodity brokers) that I depend on without fully understanding what they do. When people have different ideas about which of these four modes of in- teracting applies to a current relationship, the result can range from blank in- comprehension to acute discomfort or outright hostility. Think about a dinner guest offering to pay the host for her meal, a person barking an order to a friend, or an employee helping himself to a shrimp off the boss's plate. Mis- understandings in which one person thinks of a transaction in terms of Equal- ity Matching and another thinks in terms of Market Pricing are even more pervasive and can be even more dangerous. They tap into very different psy- chologies, one of them intuitive and universal, the other rarefied and learned, and clashes between them have been common in economic history. Economists refer to "the physical fallacy": the belief that an object has a true and constant value, as opposed to being worth only what someone is will- ing to pay for it at a given place and time.47 This is simply the difference be- tween the Equality Matching and Market Pricing mentalities. The physical fallacy may not arise when three chickens are exchanged for one knite, but when the exchanges are mediated by money, credit, and third parties, the fal- lacy can have ugly consequences. The belief that goods have a "just price' im- plies that it is avaricious to charge anything higher, and the result has been mandatory pricing schemes in medieval times, communist regimes, and many Third World countries. Such attempts to work around the law of supply and demand have usually led to waste, shortages, and black markets. Another con- sequence ot the physical fallacy is the widespread practice of outlawing inter- est, which comes from the intuition that it is rapacious to demand additional money trom someone who has paid back exactly what he borrowed. Of course, the only reason people borrow at one time and repay it later is that the 234 / Know Thyself money is worth more to them at the time they borrow it than it will be at the time they repay it. So when regimes enact sweeping usury laws, people who could put money to productive use cannot get it, and everyone's standards of living go down.48 Just as the value of something may change with time, which creates a niche for lenders who move valuable things around in time, so it may change with space, which creates a niche for middlemen who move valuable things around in space. A banana is worth more to me in a store down the street than it is in a warehouse a hundred miles away, so I am willing to pay more to the grocer than I would to the importer- even though by "eliminating the middleman" I could pay less per banana. For similar reasons, the importer is willing to charge the grocer less than he would charge me. But because lenders and middlemen do not cause tangible objects to come into being, their contributions are difficult to grasp, and they are often thought of as skimmers and parasites. A recurring event in human history is the outbreak of ghettoization, confiscation, expulsion, and mob violence against middlemen, often ethnic minorities who learned to specialize in the middleman niche." The Jews in Europe are the most familiar example, but the expatriate Chinese, the Lebanese, the Armenians, and the Gujeratis and Chett- yars of India have suffered similar histories of persecution. One economist in an unusual situation showed how the physical fallacy does not depend on any unique historical circumstance but easily arises from human psychology. He watched the entire syndrome emerge before his eyes when he spent time in a World War Il prisoner-of-war camp. Every month the prisoners received identical packages from the Red Cross. A few prisoners cir- culated through the camp, trading and lending chocolates, cigarettes, and other commodities among prisoners who valued some items more than others or who had used up their own rations before the end of the month. The middle- men made a small profit from each transaction, and as a result they were deeply resented- a microcosm of the tragedy of the middleman minority. The econ- omist wrote: "The middleman's] function, and his hard work in bringing buyer and seller together, were ignored; profits were not regarded as a reward for labour, but as the result of sharp practises. Despite the fact that his very ex- istence was proof to the contrary, the middleman was held to be redundant."3 The obvious cure for the tragic shortcomings of human intuition in a high-tech world is education. And this offers priorities for educational policy: to provide students with the cognitive tools that are most important for grasp- ing the modern world and that are most unlike the cognitive tools they are born with. The perilous fallacies we have seen in this chapter, for example, would give high priority to economics, evolutionary biology, and probability and sta- tistics in any high school or college curriculum. Unfortunately, most curricula have barely changed since medieval times, and are barely changeable, because Out of Our Depths / 235 newborn to maturity cut their losses and abandoned it to die.20 The fat cheeks and precocious responsiveness in a baby's face may be an advertisement of health designed to tilt the decision in its favor.?l But the most interesting conflicts are the psychological ones, played out in family dramas. Trivers touted the liberatory nature of sociobiology by invok- ing an "underlying symmetry in our social relationships" and "submerged ac- tors in the social world."2 He was referring to women, as we will see in the chapter on gender, and to children. The theory of parent-offspring conflict says that families do not contain all-powerful, all-knowing parents and their passive, grateful children. Natural selection should have equipped children with psychological tactics allowing them to hold their own in a struggle with their parents, with neither party having a permanent upper hand. Parents have a short-lived advantage in sheer brawn, but children can fight back by being cute, whining, throwing tantrums, pulling guilt trips, tormenting their sib- lings, getting between their parents, and holding themselves hostage with the threat of self-destructive behavior.?3 As they say, insanity is hereditary: you get it from your children. Most profoundly, children do not allow their personalities to be shaped by their parents' nagging, blandishments, or attempts to serve as role models,?+ As we shall see in the chapter on children, the effect of being raised by a given pair of parents within a culture is surprisingly small: children who grow up in the same home end up no more alike in personality than children who were sepa- rated at birth; adopted siblings grow up to be no more similar than strangers. The findings flatly contradict the predictions of every theory in the history of psychology but one. Trivers alone had predicted: The offspring cannot rely on its parents for disinterested guidance. One expects the offspring to be preprogrammed to resist some parental ma- nipulation while being open to other forms. When the parent imposes an arbitrary system of reinforcement (punishment and reward) in order to manipulate the offspring to act against its own best interests, selection Will favor offspring that resist such schedules of reinforcement.?5 That children don't turn out the way their parents want is, for many people, one of the bittersweet lessons of parenthood. "Your children are not your chil- dren," wrote the poet Kahlil Gibran. "You may give them your love but not your thoughts, for they have their own thoughts,"6 The most obvious prediction of the theory of parent-offspring conflict is that parents and siblings should all have different perceptions of how the par- ents treated the siblings. Indeed, studies of the grown members of families show that most parents claim they treated their children equitably, while a The Many Roots of Our Suffering / 249 WHAT ABOUT PEOPLE who are not tied by blood or children? No one doubts that human beings make sacrifices for people who are unrelated to them. But they could do so in two different ways. Humans, like ants, could have a gung-ho superorganism thing that prompts them to do everything for the colony. The idea that people are in- stinctively communal is an important precept of the romantic doctrine of the Noble Savage. It figured in the theory of Engels and Marx that "primitive com- munism" was the first social system, in the anarchism of Peter Kropotkin (who wrote, "The ants and termites have renounced the 'Hobbesian war; and they are the better for it"), in the family-of-man utopianism of the 1960s, and in the writings of contemporary radical scientists such as Lewontin and Chomsky.41 Some radical scientists imagine that the only alternative is an Ayn Randian in- dividualism in which every man is an island. Steven Rose and the sociologist Hilary Rose, for instance, call evolutionary psychology a "right-wing libertar- an attack on collectivity."12 But the accusation is factually incorrect- as we shall see in the chapter on politics, many evolutionary psychologists are on the political left--and it is conceptually incorrect. The real alternative to romantic collectivism is not "right-wing libertarianism" but a recognition that social generosity comes from a complex suite of thoughts and emotions rooted in the logic of reciprocity. That gives it a very different psychology from the com- munal sharing practiced by social insects, human families, and cults that try to pretend they are families.13 Trivers built on arguments by Williams and Hamilton that pure, public- minded altruism--a desire to benefit the group or species at the expense of the self is unlikely to evolve among nonrelatives, because it is vulnerable to inva- sion by cheaters who prosper by enjoying the good deeds of others without contributing in turn. But as I mentioned, Trivers also showed that a measured reciprocal altruism can evolve. Reciprocators who help others who have helped them, and who shun or punish others who have failed to help them, will enjoy the benefits of gains in trade and outcompete individualists, cheaters, and pure altruists.* Humans are well equipped for the demands of reciprocal altruism. They remember each other as individuals (perhaps with the help of dedicated regions of the brain), and have an eagle eye and a flypaper memory for cheaters.4S They feel moralistic emotions_-liking, sympathy, gratitude, guilt, shame, and anger- that are uncanny implementations of the strategies for re- ciprocal altruism in computer simulations and mathematical models. Experi- ments have confirmed the prediction that people are most inclined to help a stranger when they can do so at low cost, when the stranger is in need, and When the stranger is in a position to reciprocate.* They like people who grant them favors, grant favors to those they like, feel guilty when they have withheld a possible favor, and punish those who withhold favors from them.47 The Many Roots of Our Suffering / 255 a degree of self-deception, rendering some facts and motives uncon- scious so as not to betray- by the subtle signs of self-knowledge-the deception being practiced. Thus, the conventional view that natural se- lection favors nervous systems which produce ever more accurate im- ages of the world must be a very naïve view of mental evolution.76 The conventional view may be largely correct when it comes to the physical world, which allows for reality checks by multiple observers and where mis- conceptions are likely to harm the perceiver. But as Trivers notes, it may not be correct when it comes to the self, which one can access in a way that others cannot and where misconceptions may be helpful. Sometimes parents may want to convince a child that what they are doing is for the child's own good, children may want to convince parents that they are needy rather than greedy, lovers may want to convince each other that they will always be true, and un- related folks may want to convince one another that they are worthy coopera- tors. These opinions are often embellishments, if not tall tales, and to slip them beneath a partner's radar a speaker should believe in them so as not to stam- mer, sweat, or trip himself up in contradictions. Ice-veined liars might, of course, get away with telling bald fibs to strangers, but they would also have trouble keeping friends, who could never take their promises seriously. The price of looking credible is being unable to lie with a straight face, and that means a part of the mind must be designed to believe its own propaganda- while another part registers just enough truth to keep the self-concept in touch with reality. The theory of self-deception was foreshadowed by the sociologist Erving Goffman in his 1959 book The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life, which dis- puted the romantic notion that behind the masks we show other people is the one true self. No, said Goffman; it's masks all the way down. Many discoveries in the ensuing decades have borne him out." Though modern psychologists and psychiatrists tend to reject orthodox Freudian theory, many acknowledge that Freud was right about the defense mechanisms of the ego. Any therapist will tell you that people protest too much, deny or repress unpleasant facts, project their flaws onto others, turn their discomfort into abstract intellectual problems, distract themselves with time-consuming activities, and rationalize away their motives. The psychia- trists Randolph Nesse and Alan Lloyd have argued that these habits do not safeguard the self against bizarre sexual wishes and fears (like having sex with one's mother) but are tactics of self-deception: they suppress evidence that we are not as beneficent or competent as we would like to think.78 As Jeff Gold- blum said in The Big Chill, "Rationalizations are more important than sex." When his friends demurred, he asked, "Have you ever gone a week without a rationalization?" 264 / Know Thyself A woman is cleaning out her closet, and she finds her old American lag. she doesn't want the flag anymore, so she cuts it up into pieces and uses the rags to clean her bathroom. A family's dog was killed by a car in front of their house. They had heard that dog meat was delicious, so they cut up the dog's body and cooked it and ate it for dinner. A man goes to the supermarket once a week and buys a dead chicken. But before cooking the chicken, he has sexual intercourse with it. Then he cooks it and eats it. Many moral philosophers would say that there is nothing wrong with these acts, because private acts among consenting adults that do not harm other sen- tient beings are not immoral. Some might criticize the acts using a more sub- tle argument having to do with commitments to policies, but the infractions would still be deemed minor compared with the truly heinous acts of which people are capable. But for everyone else, such argumentation is beside the point. People have gut feelings that give them emphatic moral convictions, and they struggle to rationalize the convictions after the fact.3 These convictions may have little to do with moral judgments that one could justify to others in terms of their effects on happiness or suffering. They arise instead from the neurobiological and evolutionary design of the organs we call moral emotions. HAIDT HAS RECENTLY compiled a natural history of the emotions making up the moral sense.* The four major families are just what we would expect from Trivers's theory of reciprocal altruism and the computer models of the evolution of cooperation that followed. The other-condemning emotions- contempt, anger, and disgust- prompt one to punish cheaters. The other- praising emotions gratitude and an emotion that may be called elevation, moral awe, or being moved- prompt one to reward altruists. The other- suffering emotions-_-sympathy, compassion, and empathy- prompt one to help a needy beneficiary. And the self-conscious emotions-_guilt, shame, and embarrassment- prompt one to avoid cheating or to repair its effects. Cutting across these sets of emotions we find a distinction among three spheres of morality, each of which frames moral judgments in a different way. The ethic of autonomy pertains to an individual's interests and rights. It em- Phasizes fairness as the cardinal virtue, and is the core of morality as it is un- derstood by secular educated people in Western cultures. The ethic of community pertains to the mores of the social group; it includes values like duty, respect, adherence to convention, and deference to a hierarchy. The ethic of divinity pertains to a sense of exalted purity and holiness, which is opposed to a sense of contamination and defilement. The Sanctimonious Animal / 271 The autonomy-community-divinity trichotomy was first developed by the anthropologist Richard Shweder, who noted that non-Western traditions have rich systems of beliefs and values with all the hallmarks of moralizing but without the Western concept of individual rights. The elaborate Hindu beliefs surrounding purification are a prime example. Haidt and the py. chologist Paul Rozin have built on Shweder's work, but they have interpreted the moral spheres not as arbitrary cultural variants but as universal mental faculties with different evolutionary origins and functions.? They show that the moral spheres differ in their cognitive content, their homologues in other animals, their physiological correlates, and their neural underpin- nings. Anger, for example, which is the other-condemning emotion in the sphere of autonomy, evolved from systems for aggression and was recruited to imple- ment the cheater-punishment strategy demanded by reciprocal altruism. Dis- gust, the other-condemning emotion in the sphere of divinity, evolved from a system for avoiding biological contaminants like disease and spoilage. It may have been recruited to demarcate the moral circle that divides entities that we engage morally (such as peers) from those we treat instrumentally (such as an- imals) and those we actively avoid (such as people with a contagious disease). Embarrassment, the self-conscious emotion in the sphere of community, is a dead ringer for the gestures of appeasement and submission found in other primates. The reason that dominance got melded with morality in the first place is that reciprocity depends not only on a person's willingness to grant and return favors but on that person's ability to do so, and dominant people have that ability. Relativists might interpret the three spheres of morality as showing that individual rights are a parochial Western custom and that we should respect other cultures' ethics of community and divinity as equally valid alternatives. I conclude instead that the design of the moral sense leaves people in all cul- tures vulnerable to confusing defensible moral judgments with irrelevant pas- sions and prejudices. The ethic of autonomy or fairness is in fact not uniquely Western; Amartya Sen and the legal scholar Mary Ann Glendon have shown that it also has deep roots in Asian thought." Conversely, the ethic of commu- nity and the ethic of divinity are pervasive in the West. The ethic of commu- nity, which equates morality with a conformity to local norms, underlies the cultural relativism that has become boilerplate on college campuses. Several scholars have noticed that their students are unequipped to explain why Nazis m was wrong, because the students feel it is impermissible to criticize the values of another culture.° (I can confirm that students today reflexively hedge their moral judgments, saying things like, "Our society puts a high value on being good to other people.") Donald Symons comments on the way that peo- 272 / Know Thyself ple's judgments can do a backhip when they switch from autonomy- to community-based morality: If only one person in the world held down a terrified, struggling, screaming little girl, cut off her genitals with a septic blade, and sewed her back up, leaving only a tiny hole for urine and menstrual flow, the only question would be how severely that person should be punished, and whether the death penalty would be a sufficiently severe sanction. But when millions of people do this, instead of the enormity being mag- nified millions-fold, suddenly it becomes "culture," and thereby magi cally becomes less, rather than more, horrible, and is even defended by some Western "moral thinkers," including feminists.? The ethic of community also includes a deference to an established hier- archy, and the mind (including the Western mind) all too easily conflates pres- tige with morality. We see it in words that implicitly equate status with virtue--chivalrous, classy, gentlemanly, honorable, noble- and low rank with sin-low-class, low-rent, mean, nasty, shabby, shoddy, villain (originally mean- ing "peasant"), vulgar. The Myth of the Noble Noble is obvious in contempo- rary celebrity worship. Members of the royalty like Princess Diana and her American equivalent, John F. Kennedy Jr., are awarded the trappings of saint- hood even though they were morally unexceptional people (yes, Diana sup- ported charities, but that's pretty much the job description of a princess in this day and age). Their good looks brighten their halos even more, because people judge attractive men and women to be more virtuous.' Prince Charles, who also supports charities, will never be awarded the trappings of sainthood, even if he dies a tragic death. People also confuse morality with purity, even in the secular West. Re- member from Chapter 1 that many words for cleanliness and dirt are also words for virtue and sin (pure, unblemished, tainted, and so on). Haidt's sub- jects seem to have conflated contamination with sin when they condemned eating a dog, having sex with a dead chicken, and enjoying consensual incest (which reflects our instinctive repulsion toward sex with siblings, an emotion that evolved to deter inbreeding). The mental mix-up of the good and the clean can have ugly consequences. Racism and sexism are often expressed as a desire to avoid pollutants, as in the ostracism of the "untouchable" caste in India, the sequestering of men- struating women in Orthodox Judaism, the fear of contracting AIDS from ca- sual contact with gay men, the segregated facilities for eating, drinking, bathing, and sleeping under the Jim Crow and apartheid policies, and the "racial hygiene" laws in Nazi Germany. One of the haunting questions of The Sanctimonious Animal / 273 fire stations, stop funding social programs, medical research, foreign aid, and national defense, or raise the income tax rate to 99 percent, if that is what it would have cost to protect the environment. Tetlock observes that these fiascos came about because any politician who honestly presented the inexorable tradeoffs would be crucified for violating a taboo. He would be guilty of "tolerating poisons in our food and water," or worse, "putting a dollar value on human life." Policy analysts note that we are stuck with wasteful and inegalitarian entitlement programs because any politi- cian who tried to reform them would be committing political suicide. Savvy opponents would frame the reform in the language of taboo: "breaking our faith with the elderly," "betraying the sacred trust of veterans who risked their lives for their country," "scrimping on the care and education of the young." In the Preface, I called the Blank Slate a sacred doctrine and human nature a modern taboo. This can now be stated as a technical hypothesis. The thrust of the radical science movement was to moralize the scientific study of the mind and to engage the mentality of taboo. Recall, from Part Il, the indignant outrage, the punishment of heretics, the refusal to consider claims as they were actually stated, the moral cleansing through demonstrations and manifestos and public denunciations. Weizenbaum condemned ideas "whose very con- templation ought to give rise to feelings of disgust" and denounced the less- than-human scientists who "can even think of such a thing." But of course it is the job of scholars to think about things, even if only to make it clear why they are wrong. Moralization and scholarship thus often find themselves on a colli- sion course. THIS RUTHLESS DISSECTION Of the human moral sense does not mean that morality is a sham or that every moralist is a self-righteous prig. Moral psy- chology may be steeped in emotion, but then many philosophers have argued that morality cannot be grounded in reason alone anyway. As Hume wrote, '.'Tis not contrary to reason to prefer the destruction of the whole world to the scratching of my finger"7 The emotions of sympathy, gratitude, and guilt are the source of innumerable acts of kindness great and small, and a measured righteous anger and ethical certitude must have sustained great moral leaders throughout history. Glover notes that many twentieth-century atrocities were set in motion when the moral emotions were disabled. Decent people were lulled into com- mitting appalling acts by a variety of amoralizing causes, such as utopian ide- ologies, phased decisions (in which the targets of bombing might shift from isolated factories to factories near neighborhoods to the neighborhoods them- selves), and the diffusion of responsibility within a bureaucracy. It was often law moral sentiment- feeling empathy for victims, or asking oneself the moral-identity question "Am I the kind of person who could do this?" -that The Sanctimonious Animal | 279 tries. In any case, only a bookworm who has never actually seen an American movie or television program could believe that they glorify murderous fanat- is like Timothy McVeigh or teenagers who randomly shoot classmates in high school cafeterias. Masculine heroes in the mass media are highly moralistic: they fight bad guys. Among conservative politicians and liberal health professionals alike it is an article of faith that violence in the media is a major cause of American vio- lent crime. The American Medical Association, the American Psychological Association, and the American Academy of Pediatrics testified before Con- gress that over 3,500 studies had investigated the connection and only 18 failed to find one. Any social scientist can smell fishy numbers here, and the psy- chologist Jonathan Freedman decided to look for himself. In fact, only two hundred studies have looked for a connection between media violence and vi- olent behavior, and more than half failed to find one.22 The others found cor- relations that are small and readily explainable in other ways--for example, that violent children seek out violent entertainment, and that children are temporarily aroused (but not permanently affected) by action-packed footage. Freedman and several other psychologists who have reviewed the lit- erature have concluded that exposure to media violence has little or no effect on violent behavior in the world.? Reality checks from recent history suggest the same thing. People were more violent in the centuries before television and movies were invented. Canadians watch the same television shows as Ameri- cans but have a fourth their homicide rate. When the British colony of St. He- lena installed television for the first time in 1995, its people did not become more violent.? Violent computer games took off in the 1990s, a time when crime rates plummeted. What about the other usual suspects? Guns, discrimination, and poverty play a role in violence, but in no case is it a simple or decisive one. Guns surely make it easier for people to kill, and harder for them to de-escalate a fight be- fore a death occurs, and thus multiply the lethality of conflicts large and small. Nonetheless, many societies had sickening rates of violence before guns were invented, and people do not automatically kill one another just because they have access to guns. The Israelis and Swiss are armed to the teeth but have low rates of violent personal crime, and among American states, Maine and North Dakota have the lowest homicide rates but almost every home has a gun.? The idea that guns increase lethal crime, though certainly plausible, has been so difficult to prove that in 1998 the legal scholar John Lott published a book of statistical analyses with a title that flaunts the opposite conclusion: More Guns, Less Crime. Even if he is wrong, as I suspect he is, it is not so easy to show that more guns mean more crime. As for discrimination and poverty, again it is hard to show a direct cause- and-effect relationship. Chinese immigrants to California in the nineteenth Violence / 311 course even more calculating. Most people today live their adult lives without ever pressing their violence buttons. So what is the evidence that our species may have evolved mechanisms for discretionary violence? The first thing to keep in mind is that aggression is an organized, goal-directed activity, not the kind of event that could come from a random malfunction. If your lawnmower continued to run after you released the handle and it injured your foot, you might suspect a sticky switch or other breakdown. But if the lawnmower lay in wait until you emerged from the garage and then chased you around the yard, you would have to conclude that someone had installed a chip that programmed it to do so. The presence of deliberate chimpicide in our chimpanzee cousins raises the possibility that the forces of evolution, not just the idiosyncrasies of a par- ticular human culture, prepared us for violence. And the ubiquity of violence in human societies throughout history and prehistory is a stronger hint that we are so prepared. When we look at human bodies and brains, we find more direct signs of design for aggression. The larger size, strength, and upper-body mass of men is a zoological giveaway of an evolutionary history of violent male-male com- petition.* Other signs include the effects of testosterone on dominance and violence (which we will encounter in the chapter on gender), the emotion of anger (complete with reflexive baring of the canine teeth and clenching of the fists), the revealingly named fight-or-flight response of the autonomic ner- vous system, and the fact that disruptions of inhibitory systems of the brain (by alcohol, damage to the frontal lobe or amygdala, or defective genes in- volved in serotonin metabolism) can lead to aggressive attacks, initiated by circuits in the limbic system. 12 Boys in all cultures spontaneously engage in rough-and-tumble play, which is obviously practice for fighting. They also divide themselves into co- alitions that compete aggressively (calling to mind the remark attributed to the Duke of Wellington that "the Battle of Waterloo was won upon the playing fields of Eton").43 And children are violent well before they have been infected by war toys or cultural stereotypes. The most violent age is not adolescence but toddlerhood: in a recent large study, almost half the boys just past the age of two, and a slightly smaller percentage of the girls, engaged in hitting, biting, and kicking. As the author pointed out, "Babies do not kill each other, because we do not give them access to knives and guns. The question ... we've been trying to answer for the past 30 years is how do children learn to aggress. [But) that's the wrong question. The right question is how do they learn not to aggress." Violence continues to preoccupy the mind throughout life. According to independent surveys in several countries by the psychologists Douglas Ken- rick and David Buss, more than 80 percent of women and 90 percent of men 316/ Hot Buttons fathers nor in the homes of their husbands; unprotected, lonely, and out of sync with their inborn nature. Some women positively welcome this state of affairs, but most do not."8 There is, in fact, no incompatibility between the principles of feminism and the possibility that men and women are not psychologically identical. To repeat: equality is not the empirical claim that all groups of humans are inter- changeable; it is the moral principle that individuals should not be judged or constrained by the average properties of their group. In the case of gender, the barely defeated Equal Rights Amendment put it succinctly: "Equality of Rights under the law shall not be denied or abridged by the United States or any state on account of sex." If we recognize this principle, no one has to spin myths about the indistinguishability of the sexes to justify equality. Nor should any- one invoke sex differences to justify discriminatory policies or to hector women into doing what they don't want to do. In any case, what we do know about the sexes does not call for any action that would penalize or constrain one sex or the other. Many psychological traits relevant to the public sphere, such as general intelligence, are the same on average for men and women, and virtually all psychological traits may be found in varying degrees among the members of each sex. No sex difference yet discovered applies to every last man compared with every last woman, so generalizations about a sex will always be untrue of many individuals. And no- tions like "proper role" and "natural place" are scientifically meaningless and give no grounds for restricting freedom. Despite these principles, many feminists vehemently attack research on sexuality and sex differences. The politics of gender is a major reason that the application of evolution, genetics, and neuroscience to the human mind is bit- terly resisted in modern intellectual life. But unlike other human divisions such as race and ethnicity, where any biological differences are minor at most and scientifically uninteresting, gender cannot possibly be ignored in the science of human beings. The sexes are as old as complex life and are a fundamental topic in evolutionary biology, genetics, and behavioral ecology. To disregard them in the case of our own species would be to make a hash of our understanding of our place in the cosmos. And of course differences between men and women affect every aspect of our lives. We all have a mother and a father, are attracted to members of the opposite sex (or notice our contrast with the people who are), and are never unaware of the sex of our siblings, children, and friends. To ignore gender would be to ignore a major part of the human condition. The goal of this chapter is to clarify the relation between the biology of human nature and current controversies on the sexes, including the two most incendiary, the gender gap and sexual assault. With both of these hot buttons, I will argue against the conventional wisdom associated with certain people who claim to speak on behalf of feminism. That may create an illusion that the 340 / Hot Buttons have higher levels than nonviolent criminals; trial lawyers have higher lev. els than those who push paper. The relations are complicated for a num- ber of reasons. Over a broad range of values, the concentration of testosterone in the bloodstream doesn't matter. Some traits, such as spatial abilities, peak at moderate rather than high levels. The effects of testos- terone depend on the number and distribution of receptors for the mole- cule, not just on its concentration. And one's psychological state can affect testosterone levels as well as the other way around. But there is a causal re- lation, albeit a complicated one. When women preparing for a sex-change operation are given androgens, they improve on tests of mental rotation and get worse on tests of verbal fluency. The journalist Andrew Sullivan, whose medical condition had lowered his testosterone levels, describes the effects of injecting it: "The rush of a T shot is not unlike the rush of going on a first date or speaking before an audience. I feel braced. After one in- jection, I almost got in a public brawl for the first time in my life. There is always a lust peak- every time it takes me unaware."S Though testos- terone levels in men and women do not overlap, variations in level have similar kinds of effects in the two sexes. High-testosterone women smile less often and have more extramarital affairs, a stronger social presence, and even a stronger handshake. • Women's cognitive strengths and weaknesses vary with the phase of their menstrual cycle.* When estrogen levels are high, women get even better at tasks on which they typically do better than men, such as verbal fluency. When the levels are low, women get better at tasks on which men typically do better, such as mental rotation. A variety of sexual motives, including their taste in men, vary with the menstrual cycle as well.47 • Androgens have permanent effects on the developing brain, not just tran- sient effects on the adult brain. 1% Girls with congenital adrenal hyperpla- sia overproduce androstenedione, the androgen hormone made famous by the baseball slugger Mark McGwire. Though their hormone levels are brought to normal soon after birth, the girls grow into tomboys, with more rough-and-tumble play, a greater interest in trucks than dolls, better spatial abilities, and, when they get older, more sexual fantasies and at- tractions involving other girls. Those who are treated with hormones only later in childhood show male patterns of sexuality when they become young adults, including quick arousal by pornographic images, an au- tonomous sex drive centered on genital stimulation, and the equivalent of wet dreams.19 • The ultimate fantasy experiment to separate biology from socialization would be to take a baby boy, give him a sex-change operation, and have his parents raise him as a girl and other people treat him as one. If gender is socially constructed, the child should have the mind of a normal girl; if it 348 / Hot Buttons too obvious. The movements are based on a false theory of human psychology, the Blank Slate. They fail to apply their most vaunted ability--stripping away pretense to themselves. And they take all the fun out of art! Modernism and postmodernism cling to a theory of perception that was rejected long ago: that the sense organs present the brain with a tableau of raw colors and sounds and that everything else in perceptual experience is a learned social construction. As we saw in preceding chapters, the visual system of the brain comprises some fifty regions that take raw pixels and effortlessly organize them into surfaces, colors, motions, and three-dimensional objects. We can no more turn the system off and get immediate access to pure sensory experience than we can override our stomachs and tell them when to release their digestive enzymes. The visual system, moreover, does not drug us into a hallucinatory fantasy disconnected from the real world. It evolved to feed us information about the consequential things out there, like rocks, cliffs, ani- mals, and other people and their intentions. Nor does innate organization stop at apprehending the physical structure of the world. It also colors our visual experience with universal emotions and aesthetic pleasures. Young children prefer calendar landscapes to pictures of deserts and forests, and babies as young as three months old gaze longer at a pretty face than at a plain one.4 Babies prefer consonant musical intervals over dissonant ones, and two-year-olds embark on a lifetime of composing and appreciating narrative fiction when they engage in pretend play.5o When we perceive the products of other people's behavior, we evaluate them through our intuitive psychology, our theory of mind. We do not take a stretch of language or an artifact like a product or work of art at face value, but try to guess why the producers came out with them and what effect they hope to have on us (as we saw in Chapter 12). Of course, people can be taken in by a clever liar, but they are not trapped in a false world of words and images and in need of rescue by postmodernist artists. Modernist and postmodernist artists and critics fail to acknowledge an- other feature of human nature that drives the arts: the hunger for status, espe- cially their own hunger for status. As we saw, the psychology of art is entangled with the psychology of esteem, with its appreciation of the rare, the sumptu- ous, the virtuosic, and the dazzling. The problem is that whenever people seek rare things, entrepreneurs make them less rare, and whenever a dazzling per- formance is imitated, it can become commonplace. The result is the perennial turnover of styles in the arts. The psychologist Colin Martindale has docu- mented that every art form increases in complexity, ornamentation, and emo- tonal charge until the evocative potential of the style is fully exploited." Attention then turns to the style itself, at which point the style gives way to à new one. Martindale attributes this cycle to habituation on the part of the au- dience, but it also comes from the desire for attention on the part of the artists. 412 / Hot Buttons Once again, postmodernism took this extreme to an even greater extreme in which the theory upstaged the subject matter and became a genre of per- formance art in itselt. Postmodernist scholars, taking off from the critical the- orists Theodor Adorno and Michel Foucault, distrust the demand for "inguistic transpareney" because it hobbles the ability "to think the world more radically" and puts a text in danger of being turned into a mass-market commodity.»° This attitude has made them regular winners of the annual Bad Writing Contest, which "celebrates the most stylistically lamentable passages found in scholarly books and articles."' In 1998, first prize went to the lauded professor of rhetoric at Berkeley, Judith Butler, for the following sentence; The move from a structuralist account in which capital is understood to structure social relations in relatively homologous ways to a view of hegemony in which power relations are subject to repetition, conver- gence, and rearticulation brought the question of temporality into the thinking of structure, and marked a shift from a form of Althusserian theory that takes structural totalities as theoretical objects to one in which the insights into the contingent possibility of structure inaugu- rate a renewed conception of hegemony as bound up with the contin- gent sites and strategies of the rearticulation of power. Dutton, whose journal Philosophy and Literature sponsors the contest, assures us that this is not a satire. The rules of the contest forbid it: "Deliberate parody cannot be allowed in a field where unintended self-parody is so widespread." A final blind spot to human nature is the failure of contemporary artists and theorists to deconstruct their own moral pretensions. Artists and critics have long believed that an appreciation of elite art is ennobling and have spo- ken of cultural philistines in tones ordinarily reserved for child molesters (as We see in the two meanings of the word barbarian). The affectation of social reform that surrounds modernism and postmodernism is part of this tradi- tion. Though moral sophistication requires an appreciation of history and cul- tural diversity, there is no reason to think that the elite arts are a particularly good way to instill it compared with middlebrow realistic fiction or traditional education. The plain fact is that there are no obvious moral consequences to how people entertain themselves in their leisure time. The conviction that artists and connoisseurs are morally advanced is a cognitive illusion, arising trom the fact that our circuitry for morality is cross-wired with our circuitry for status (see Chapter 15). As the critic George Steiner has pointed out, know that a man can read Goethe or Rilke in the evening, that he can play bach and Schubert, and go to his day's work at Auschwitz in the morning. Conversely there must be many unlettered people who give blood, risk their The Arts / 415 lives as volunteer firefighters, or adopt handicapped children, but whose opin- ion of modern art is "My four-year-old daughter could have done that." The moral and political track record of modernist artists is nothing to be proud of. Some were despicable in the conduct of their personal lives, and many embraced fascism or Stalinism. The modernist composer Karlheinz Stockhausen described the September 11, 2001, terrorist attacks as "the great- est work of art imaginable for the whole cosmos" and added, enviously, that "artists, too, sometimes go beyond the limits of what is feasible and conceiv- able, so that we wake up, so that we open ourselves to another world'62 Nor is the theory of postmodernism especially progressive. A denial of objective real- ity is no friend to moral progress, because it prevents one from saying, for ex- ample, that slavery or the Holocaust really took place. And as Adam Gopnik has pointed out, the political messages of most postmodernist pieces are ut- terly banal, like "racism is bad! But they are stated so obliquely that viewers are made to feel morally superior for being able to figure them out. As for sneering at the bourgeoisie, it is a sophomoric grab at status with no claim to moral or political virtue. The fact is that the values of the middle class- personal responsibility, devotion to family and neighborhood, avoid- ance of macho violence, respect for liberal democracy--are good things, not bad things. Most of the world wants to join the bourgeoisie, and most artists are members in good standing who adopted a few bohemian affectations. Given the history of the twentieth century, the reluctance of the bourgeoisie to join mass utopian uprisings can hardly be held against them. And if they want to hang a painting of a red barn or a weeping clown above their couch, it's none of our damn business. The dominant theories of elite art and criticism in the twentieth century grew out of a militant denial of human nature. One legacy is ugly, baffling, and insulting art. The other is pretentious and unintelligible scholarship. And they're surprised that people are staying away in droves? A REVOLT HAS begun. Museum-goers have become bored with the umpteenth exhibit on the female body featuring dismembered torsos or hun- dreds of pounds of lard chewed up and spat out by the artist.63 Graduate stu- dents in the humanities are grumbling in emails and conference hallways about being locked out of the job market unless they write in gibberish while randomly dropping the names of authorities like Foucault and Butler. Maver- ick scholars are doffing the blinders that prevented them from looking at ex- citing developments in the sciences of human nature. And younger artists are wondering how the art world got itself into the bizarre place in which beauty is a dirty word. These currents of discontent are coming together in a new philosophy of the arts, one that is consilient with the sciences and respectful of the minds 416 / Hot Buttons