"The Modern System of the Arts:
A Study in the History of Aesthetics Part I"
Paul Oskar Kristeller
Journal of the History of Ideas, Vol. 12, No. 4 (Oct., 1951), pp. 496-527
http://www.jstor.org/stable/2707484
http://esztetika.elte.hu/baranyistvan/files/2012/09/kristeller-modern-system-of-arts-I-1951.pdf
"The Modern System of the Arts: A Study in the History of Aesthetics Part I"
Paul Oskar Kristeller
Journal of the History of Ideas, Vol. 12, No. 4 (Oct., 1951), pp. 496-527
http://www.jstor.org/stable/2707484
http://esztetika.elte.hu/baranyistvan/files/2012/09/kristeller-modern-system-of-arts-I-1951.pdf
[498]
II
The Greek term for Art (Trxvq) and its Latin equivalent (ars) do
not specifically denote the "fine arts " in the modern sense, but were
applied to all kinds of human activities which we would call crafts or
sciences. Moreover, whereas modern aesthetics stresses the fact that
Art cannot be learned, and thus often becomes involved in the curious
endeavor to teach the unteachable, the ancients always understood by
Art something that can be taught and learned. Ancient statements
about Art and the arts have often been read and understood as if they
were meant in the modern sense of the fine arts. This may in some
[499]
cases have led to fruitful errors, but it does not do justice to the original intention of the ancient writers. When the Greek authors began
to oppose Art to Nature, they thought of human activity in general.
When Hippocrates contrasts Art with Life, he is thinking of medicine, and when his comparison is repeated by Goethe or Schiller with
reference to poetry, this merely shows the long way of change which
the term Art had traversed by 1800 from its original meaning.7 Plato
puts art above mere routine because it proceeds by rational principles
and rules,8 and Aristotle, who lists Art among the so-called intellectual virtues, characterizes it as a kind of activity based on knowledge,
in a definition whose influence was felt through many centuries.9
The Stoics also defined Art as a system of cognitions,10 and it was in
this sense that they considered moral virtue as an art of living.1
...
[506] classical antiquity left no systems or elaborate concepts of
an aesthetic nature,70 but merely a number of scattered notions and
suggestions that exercised a lasting influence down to modern times
but had to be carefully selected, taken out of their context, rearranged,
reemphasized and reinterpreted or misinterpreted before they could
be utilized as building materials for aesthetic systems. We have
to admit the conclusion, distasteful to many historians of aesthetics
but grudgingly admitted by most of them, that ancient writers and
thinkers, though confronted with excellent works of art and quite susceptible to their charm, were neither able nor eager to detach the
aesthetic quality of these works of art from their intellectual, moral,
religious and practical function or content, or to use such an aesthetic
quality as a standard for grouping the fine arts together or for making
them the subject of a comprehensive philosophical interpretation.
...
[509] On the other hand, the concept of beauty that is occasionally discussed by Aquinas 84 and somewhat more emphatically by a few other
medieval philosophers 85 is not linked with the arts, fine or otherwise,
but treated primarily as a metaphysical attribute of God and of his
creation, starting from Augustine and from Dionysius the Areopagite. Among the transcendentals or most general attributes of being,
pulchrum does not appear in thirteenth-century philosophy, although
it is considered as a general concept and treated in close connection
with bonum. The question whether Beauty is one of the transcendentals has become a subject of controversy among Neo-Thomists.86
This is an interesting sign of their varying attitude toward modern
aesthetics, which some of them would like to incorporate in a philosophical system based on Thomist principles. For Aquinas himself,
[510]
or for other medieval philosophers, the question is meaningless, for
even if they had posited pulchrum as a transcendental concept, which
they did not, its meaning would have been different from the modern
notion of artistic beauty in which the Neo-Thomists are interested.
Thus it is obvious that there was artistic production as well as artistic
appreciation in the Middle Ages,87 and this could not fail to find occasional expression in literature and philosophy. Yet there is no medieval concept or system of the Fine Arts, and if we want to keep speaking of medieval aesthetics, we must admit that its concept and subject
matter are, for better or for worse, quite different from the modern
philosophical discipline
Part II
Vol. 13, No. 1 (Jan., 1952), pp. 17-46
http://esztetika.elte.hu/baranyistvan/files/2012/09/kristeller-modern-system-of-arts-II-1952.pdf
http://www.jstor.org/stable/2707724
[43] The grouping
together of the visual arts with poetry and music into the system of
the fine arts with which we are familiar did not exist in classical
antiquity, in the Middle Ages or in the Renaissance. However, the
ancients contributed to the modern system the comparison between
poetry and painting, and the theory of imitation that established a
[44]
kind of link between painting and sculpture, poetry and music. The
Renaissance brought about the emancipation of the three major visual
arts from the crafts, it multiplied the comparisons between the various arts, especially between painting and poetry, and it laid the
ground for an amateur interest in the different arts that tended to
bring them together from the point of view of the reader, spectator
and listener rather than of the artist. The seventeenth century witnessed the emancipation of the natural sciences and thus prepared the
way for a clearer separation between the arts and the sciences. Only
the early eighteenth century, especially in England and France, produced elaborate treatises written by and for amateurs in which the
various fine arts were grouped together, compared with each other
and combined in a systematic scheme based on common principles.
The second half of the century, especially in Germany, took the additional step of incorporating the comparative and theoretical treatment
of the fine arts as a separate discipline into the system of philosophy.
The modern system of the fine arts is thus pre-romantic in its origin,
although all romantic as well as later aesthetics takes this system as
its necessary basis.
It is not easy to indicate the causes for the genesis of the system
in the eighteenth century. The rise of painting and of music since
the Renaissance, not so much in their actual achievements as in their
prestige and appeal, the rise of literary and art criticism, and above
all the rise of an amateur public to which art collections and exhibitions, concerts as well as opera and theatre performances were
addressed, must be considered as important factors. The fact that the
affinity between the various fine arts is more plausible to the amateur,
who feels a comparable kind of enjoyment, than to the artist himself,
who is concerned with the peculiar aims and techniques of his art, is
obvious in itself and is confirmed by Goethe's reaction. The origin
of modern aesthetics in amateur criticism would go a long way to
explain why works of art have until recently been analyzed by aestheticians from the point of view of the spectator, reader and listener
rather than of the producing artist.
The development we have been trying to understand also provides
an interesting object lesson for the historian of philosophy and of
ideas in general. We are accustomed to the process by which notions
first formulated by great and influential thinkers are gradually diffused among secondary writers and finally become the common property of the general public. Such seems to have been the development
of aesthetics from Kant to the present. Its history before Kant is of
a very different kind. The basic questions and conceptions under-
[45]
lying modern aesthetics seem to have originated quite apart from the
traditions of systematic philosophy or from the writings of important
original authors. They had their inconspicuous beginnings in secondary authors, now almost forgotten though influential in their own
time, and perhaps in the discussions and conversations of educated
laymen reflected in their writings. These notions had a tendency to
fluctuate and to grow slowly, but only after they had crystallized into
a pattern that seemed generally plausible did they find acceptance
among the greater authors and the systematic philosophers. Baumgarten's aesthetics was but a program, and Kant's aesthetics the
philosophical elaboration of a body of ideas that had had almost a
century of informal and non-philosophical growth. If the absence of
the scheme of the fine arts before the eighteenth century and its
fluctuations in that century have escaped the attention of most historians, this merely proves how thoroughly and irresistibly plausible
the scheme has become to modern thinkers and writers.
he various arts are certainly as old as human civilization, but the
manner in which we are accustomed to group them and to assign them
a place in our scheme of life and of culture is comparatively recent.
This fact is not as strange as may appear on the surface. In the
course of history, the various arts change not only their content and
style, but also their relations to each other, and their place in the
general system of culture, as do religion, philosophy or science. Our
familiar system of the five fine arts not merely originated in the eighteenth century, but it also reflects the particular cultural and social
conditions of that time. If we consider other times and places, the
status of the various arts, their associations and their subdivisions
appear very different. There were important periods in cultural history when the novel, instrumental music, or canvas painting did not
exist or have any importance. On the other hand, the sonnet and the
epic poem, stained glass and mosaic, fresco painting and book illumination, vase painting and tapestry, bas relief and pottery have all
been " major " arts at various times and in a way they no longer are
now. Gardening has lost its standing as a fine art since the eighteenth
century. On the other hand, the moving picture is a good example of
how new techniques may lead to modes of artistic expression for
which the aestheticians of the eighteenth and nineteenth century had
no place in their systems. The branches of the arts all have their rise
and decline, and even their birth and death, and the distinction between "major" arts and their subdivisions is arbitrary and subject
to change. There is hardly any ground but critical tradition or philo-
[46]
sophical preference for deciding whether engraving is a separate art
(as most of the eighteenth-century authors believed) or a subdivision
of painting, or whether poetry and prose, dramatic and epic poetry,
instrumental and vocal music are separate arts or subdivisions of one
major art.
As a result of such changes, both in modern artistic production
and in the study of other phases of cultural history, the traditional
system of the fine arts begins to show signs of disintegration. Since
the latter part of the nineteenth century, painting has moved further
away from literature than at any previous time, whereas music has at
times moved closer to it, and the crafts have taken great strides to
recover their earlier standing as decorative arts. A greater awareness
of the different techniques of the various arts has produced dissatisfaction among artists and critics with the conventions of an aesthetic
system based on a situation no longer existing, an aesthetics that is
trying in vain to hide the fact that its underlying system of the fine
arts is hardly more than a postulate and that most of its theories are
abstracted from particular arts, usually poetry, and more or less inapplicable to the others. The excesses of aestheticism have led to a
healthy reaction which is yet far from universal. The tendency
among some contemporary philosophers to consider Art and the
aesthetic realm as a pervasive aspect of human experience rather than
as the specific domain of the conventional fine arts also goes a long
way to weaken the latter notion in its traditional form.279 All these
ideas are still fluid and ill defined, and it is difficult to see how far they
will go in modifying or undermining the traditional status of the fine
arts and of aesthetics. In any case, these contemporary changes may
help to open our eyes to an understanding of the historical origins and
limitations of the modern system of the fine arts. Conversely, such
historical understanding might help to free us from certain conventional preconceptions and to clarify our ideas on the present status
and future prospects of the arts and of aesthetics.
...
...
...